Wikijunior:Philosophy/Print version


Philosophy

The current, editable version of this book is available in Wikibooks, the open-content textbooks collection, at
https://en.wikibooks.org/wiki/Philosophy

Permission is granted to copy, distribute, and/or modify this document under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0 License.

What is Philosophy

What is Philosophy?

Philosophy is a hard word to define. This is because philosophers themselves disagree on what it means. 'Philosophy' comes from two Greek words: 'Philos' (φιλος), or 'love of'; and 'Sophia' (σοφια), or 'wisdom'. Wisdom is an understanding of what is true.

Method

edit

Review

edit

Terms:

  • Philosophy
  • Wisdom


Western Philosophy

Western Philosophy

Western philosophy is a tradition of philosophy that has its origins in Ancient Greece. Its founding figures include Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle.

Classical Philosophy

edit
  • Socrates
  • Plato
  • Aristotle
  • Epicurus
  • Stoicism

Medieval Philosophy

edit
  • St. Augustine
  • Anselm
  • Thomas Aquinas
  • William of Ockham

Modern Philosophy

edit
  • Rationalism
    • René Descartes
    • Baruch Spinoza
    • Gottfried Leibniz
  • Empiricism
    • John Locke
    • George Berkeley
    • David Hume
  • Immanuel Kant
  • Post-Kant
    • G.W.F. Hegel
    • Søren Kierkegaard
    • Friedrich Nietzsche
    • John Stuart Mill

Contemporary Philosophy

edit
  • Analytic Philosophy
    • Bertrand Russell
    • Ludwig Wittgenstein
    • Daniel Dennett
    • Peter Singer
  • Continental Philosophy
    • Jean-Paul Sartre


Indian Philosophy

Indian Philosophy

Indian philosophy (a.k.a. dharmic philosophy) is the set of philosophical and religious traditions hailing from the Indian subcontinent.

Hinduism

edit

Buddhism

edit

Jainism

edit

Sikhism

edit


Chinese Philosophy

There are many schools of philosophy in China. The most important schools are Confucianism and Taoism. They were started by Confucius and Lao-Tzu respectively. In the Eastern Zhou Dynasty, there were so many schools of thoughts that people called it the Contention of a Hundred Schools of Thoughts.

Confucianism

edit

Taosim

edit

Legalism

edit

Mohism

edit


Ethics

Ethics

Ethics is the study of what are the right and wrong ways to act. The central question of ethics is "How should I live?"

Theories of ethics

edit

There are three main ways that philosophers usually approach this question.

First is the concept of virtue ethics. Virtue ethics believes that an action is right or wrong because of what it says about the character of the person doing the acting (that person's virtue). So if someone lies, virtue ethics would ask what it says about that person's character.

Deontology is the view that ethics is a matter of duty and rules. It says that what's important is to consider whether a person's actions are right or wrong. For example, it would be wrong to murder because the act of murdering is bad.

Consequentialism is the idea that what ultimately matters is the consequences of actions. If someone steals from someone else, consequentialism might say this is wrong because the person who was stolen from would be unhappy.

While each of these approaches may seem like good ideas, the problem arises when we consider situations in which they conflict with one another. Imagine for example a situation in which killing one person would save many people. A virtue ethicist would ask what kind of person would murder another person. Someone who subscribes to deontology might say that murder is wrong no matter what. And a consequentialist might say that the lives of many people outweigh the life of one person. Situations in which different ethical positions conflict are called moral dilemmas, and they are talked about to show why one ethical theory has strengths or weaknesses compared to another one.

Meta-ethics

edit

The debate between the three theories is called normative ethics, and it's a major branch of the study of ethics. Two other important branches that we will talk about are meta-ethics and applied ethics. Meta-ethics is the branch of ethics which asks what 'right' or 'wrong' even means. It is an inquiry into the concept known as value, which is what people take to be desirable, or good.

Review

edit

Terms:

  • Consequentialism: the ethical theory that good is defined by the consequences of actions.
  • Deontology: the ethical theory that good is defined by actions.
  • Ethics: the study of what are the right and wrong ways to act.
  • Good:
  • Moral agent:
  • Moral dilemma: a situation in which different ethical positions conflict.
  • Virtue: the character of a moral agent.
  • Virtue ethics: the ethical theory that good is defined by the character of a moral agent.


Epistemology

Epistemology

Epistemology is the study of how we know what we know.

What is Knowledge?

edit

The fundamental question that epistemology wants to answer is what knowledge is. A definition of knowledge that many philosophers have used is justified true belief. That is, you know something if:

  1. You believe it to be true. Obviously, you can't know the sky is blue if you think it isn't!
  2. It actually is true. You can't know that the sky is actually purple, since it isn't.
  3. That belief is justified.

This third point is the most complicated part. What justifies beliefs? Well, philosophers have suggested some ideas:

  1. Coherentism: A belief is justified if it fits well with other beliefs you have.
  2. Foundationalism: A belief is justified if it's based on basic beliefs; beliefs that are so obvious that they don't need further justification.
  3. Reliabilism: A belief is justified if you form it through a reliable process.

So, how does our belief about the sky fall into this? Well, coherentists don't look at beliefs individually, they view them as part of a big web. Whether or not the belief that the sky is blue is justified depends on the other beliefs in your web. Let's say that you believe that your eyes are always wrong, and whatever you see is the opposite of what is true. This belief does not fit well (or cohere) with the belief that the sky is blue, because you came to that conclusion using your eyes. So, your belief that the sky is blue would not be justified. However, if you believe that your eyes are generally right, then your belief that the sky is blue would be justified, since those beliefs cohere well with each other.

To a foundationalist, this is really simple. Your eyes give you direct knowledge of what the sky looks like. It's non-inferential, meaning that it's not derived from other beliefs. You just instantly know that the sky is blue by looking at it, and this belief justifies itself.

Reliabilism is a bit different from the other two theories, because it's what's called an externalist theory, while the others are internalist theories. Internalist theories say that you must have access to the factors that justify your beliefs, whether they be immediate experience (foundationalism) or other beliefs (coherentism). Meanwhile, reliabilism is externalist, meaning that you don't need to have access to the justifying factors for your beliefs; in this case, you don't need to be aware about whether or not the process that caused you to form your belief is reliable, all that matters is that it actually is reliable. With our sky belief, it's justified as long as you aren't colorblind, hallucinating, or, for some other reason, not able to properly determine the color of the sky.

The New Evil Demon Problem

edit

One thought experiment that has been brought up a lot in the debate about what theory of justification is correct is the "new evil demon problem." It goes like this:

Imagine that there are two people, John and Jimmy, who both look up at the sky at the same time, and both see that it's blue. However, Jimmy lives in a world where an evil demon has deceived him so that he sees the sky is blue when it, in fact, is orange. Meanwhile, John is in a world where the sky is blue. They both form this belief (and all of their other beliefs) through the exact same process, and otherwise have completely identical mental states, but all of Jimmy's beliefs are the opposite of the truth, due to the evil demon.

The question is, are Jimmy's beliefs justified?

Coherentists say yes, since he believes that he isn't being deceived, and that coheres well with his belief that, say, the sky is blue. Foundationalists also say yes, since the belief is formed through his ordinary sensory experience, which produces basic beliefs. Reliabilists, however, say no, since all of his beliefs are false, meaning that the process in question is not reliable. Which do you think?

The Gettier Problem

edit

Recently, the "justified true belief" definition of knowledge has become less popular, due to what are called Gettier cases. Here is an example:

 

You see the clock to your right, that says that it's 2:00. This makes you believe that it is 2:00, and it is in fact 2:00 at that time. However, the clock is actually broken, and always displays 2:00 no matter what the time is. It's just by a sheer coincidence that you happened to look at it when it was exactly 2:00.

Here, you do believe that it's 2:00, it is true that it's 2:00, and this belief is justified, because you based it on what the clock said; this coheres well with your belief that clocks are generally reliable, so it's fine for coherentists, clocks actually are generally reliable, so it's fine for reliabilists, and it's based on your immediate experience of the clock, so it's non-inferentially justified for foundationalists. But, do you really know that it's 2:00? Your belief is true essentially by accident, and there was no connection between your justification and why the belief was actually true. So, this suggests that knowledge is more than just justified true belief.

Some people have suggested ways to get around this:

  1. The No-False-Lemmas (NFL) Condition: This adds one more requirement to knowledge beyond justification, truth, and belief. This extra requirement is that the belief must not be based on any false beliefs. For instance, your clock belief is not knowledge, since it requires you to falsely believe that this clock is not broken.
  2. The Tracking Theory: This theory, popularized by philosopher Robert Nozick, replaces the requirement for justification with sensitivity and adherence requirements. Sensitivity means that in the closest possible world where the belief were false, you wouldn't believe it, and adherence means that in the closest possible world where the belief were true, you would still believe it. The clock belief fails the sensitivity condition since, in the closest possible world where it is false that it's 2:00, the clock would still say that it's 2:00, so you would believe that that is the time, falsely.
  3. The Causal Theory: This theory was proposed by Alvin Goldman and says that you can only know something if the factors that make the belief true in some way cause you to believe it. The clock belief fails this requirement because the fact that the clock said 2:00 was completely unrelated to the fact that it was 2:00 at the time, so your belief that it was 2:00, which arose due to the clock, is equally unrelated to that fact. However, if the clock were working, then the fact that it was 2:00 would have caused the clock to say that it was 2:00, and your belief would therefore be caused by the fact that it was indeed 2:00.
  4. The Defeasibility Condition: This adds another requirement for knowledge, similar to the NFL condition, except the defeasibility condition is that there must be no true statements ("defeaters") that would undermine one's justification for that belief, regardless of if you are aware of them or not. For instance, the clock belief is not knowledge, because you are not aware of the true statement that the clock is not working.
  5. Biting the Bullet: This is where you simply admit that the clock belief is actually knowledge. This is not a solution to the problem, but rather a "dissolution" of it. That means that this doesn't attempt to solve the problem, but instead says that it is not a problem at all.

But there is still one problem. That problem is, how do we decide which of these theories is correct? How do we decide what knowledge actually is?

The Problem of the Criterion

edit

Another name for that problem is the problem of the criterion. More formally, it's based on the relationship between two questions:

  1. What do we know (what beliefs count as knowledge)?
  2. How do we know (how can we determine what beliefs count as knowledge)?

The answer to the first question seems to assume that we know the answer to the second question, since we can't figure out what counts as knowledge if we don't know how to do that. But the answer to the second question also seems to assume that we can answer the first one, since we would need some examples of knowledge to determine what the rule that we can use to figure out what counts as knowledge is. So, we're basically going around in circles, and can't get anywhere. Or can we?

There are three main solutions to this problem:

  1. Methodism: Answer the second question first. We start with the conditions for what knowledge is, and we use that to find examples of it.
  2. Particularism: Answer the first question first. Figure out examples of knowledge, and then use those to figure out what the rule is.
  3. Skepticism: Don't answer either question, and instead come to the conclusion that we can't actually know anything.

There is no consensus as to which solution is right, but almost all philosophers agree that the last solution is wrong.


Logic

Logic

Logic is the branch of philosophy dealing with arguments.

Branches of Logic

edit

Logic is divided into two main branches: inductive and deductive logic.

Review

edit

Terms:

  • Axiomatic System- a deductive system of reasoning that starts with a relatively small number of basic principles (axioms).
  • Predicate Logic- the branch of symbolic logic that takes predicates as the fundamental units of analysis.
  • Sentential Logic- the branch of symbolic logic that takes sentences as the fundamental units of analysis.
  • Truth Preservation- the inability of a method or pattern of reasoning to take one from truths to falsehood.


References

References

This is a detailed list of all sources used.

General:

  1. Bergmann, Merrie, James Moor, and Jack Nelson. The Logic Book.
  2. Stokes, Philip. Philosophy: The Great Thinkers. London, Arcturus Publishing Limited, 2007.

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:

  1. Alexander, Larry and Moore, Michael, "Deontological Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/ethics-deontological/>.
  2. Bobzien, Susanne, "Ancient Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/logic-ancient/>.
  3. Hursthouse, Rosalind, "Virtue Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/ethics-virtue/>.
  4. Kraut, Richard, "Aristotle's Ethics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/aristotle-ethics/>.
  5. Shapiro, Stewart, "Classical Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/logic-classical/>.
  6. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, "Consequentialism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/consequentialism/>.
  7. Ichikawa, Jonathan Jenkins; Steup, Matthias (2024), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "The Analysis of Knowledge", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-12-01

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:

  1. "Epistemic Justification". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2024-12-01.
  2. "Problem of the Criterion". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2024-12-01.
  3. "Gettier Problems". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2024-12-01.