Précis of epistemology/Why is entropy real?

The reality of thermodynamic entropy edit

To know matter in all its states, entropy is one of the most fundamental and important concepts. With it we can explain almost everything, without it almost nothing. Entropy can always be assigned to the various fragments of matter as soon as very general conditions are met, to be in thermal equilibrium or close to thermal equilibrium, and it can generally be measured. From the point of view of empirical science and thermodynamic theory, entropy is a real magnitude, it describes real properties of matter. In thermodynamics courses it is said to be a state function, in order to say that it is determined by the actual state of the system. Entropy really exists, not just in the imagination of theorists.

From the point of view of statistical physics, the reality of entropy is nevertheless a problem.

Statistical entropy edit

Statistical physics asks us to distinguish two notions of state for a physical system, the microscopic state, or microstate, and the macroscopic state, or macrostate.

  • The macrostate is the state as defined by thermodynamics. It depends on macroscopic parameters: volume, internal energy, number of moles, pressure, temperature, surface tension, chemical potential, magnetization, applied external field or any other measurable macroscopic parameter which serves to determine the equilibrium state of the studied system.
  • The microstate is the instantantaneous state of the system. It depends on all the states of its microscopic constituents. In classical physics, it is determined by the positions and velocities of all constituent particles. In quantum physics, the microstate is the quantum state of the system that is determined by the Schrödinger equation.

The macrostate does not evolve or slowly and usually deterministically, the microstate usually changes all the time, very quickly and in a random way.

It seems that the real state of a system is always its microstate. The macrostate is only a rough description that ignores all the microscopic details.

Except in rare cases, one never knows exactly the microstate of a macroscopic system, because one would have to know the quantum states of all its microscopic constituents, which are far too numerous to be enumerated, and the way they are entangled.

Since the microstate is generally unknown, statistical physics reasons about the probability distribution of possible microstates. Entropy is always defined from this probability distribution. It is calculated with the Gibbs formula:

 

where the   are the probabilities of all possible microstates  .   is the Boltzmann constant.

For a quasi-isolated system, it can be shown that in equilibrium all the possible microstates are equally probable (see complement). In a somewhat mysterious way, this distribution of probabilities is called microcanonical. If   is the number of possible microstates. The   are then equal to   since they are all equal. Gibbs' formula then leads to Boltzmann's formula:

 

Boltzmann is the first (1872-1875) who defined statistical entropy. Gibbs came after and generalized the Boltzmann formula for any probability distribution (1902).

In quantum mechanics, we count the number of microstates of a basis. This number is the dimension of the space of possible microstates. When entropy is defined with a probability distribution, we can assign probabilities to the basis microstates, but it is best to reason with the density operator.

Entropy measures the lack of information on the microstate of a system, hence the ignorance of the observer. But then it seems that it is not a real magnitude since it depends on how the observer is informed. Must we conclude that thermodynamics is wrong to postulate that entropy is a function of state?

The reality of statistical entropy edit

Statistical ensembles, ergodicity and time averages edit

Statistical physics is developed in a mathematically rigorous way by reasoning on statistical ensembles of physical systems (Gibbs 1902). The probability of a micro-state is interpreted as the probability that a randomly selected system in the statistical ensemble is in this microstate.

In principle, ergodic theory allows to link the quantities defined with statistical ensembles to quantities defined with a single physical system. Ensemble averages are identified as the system time averages. But we usually reason about very long-time averages, because it takes immense time in relation to the age of the Universe for a macroscopic system to explore a significant fraction of its space of accessible microstates. Yet thermodynamic measurements are generally quite fast. As long as the systems are not too far from thermal equilibrium, a fraction of a second may suffice. We can even measure them continuously. We never wait billions of years.

If one correctly calculates an equilibrium quantity, with a suitable statistical set, the result is confirmed by the observation. But the duration of it can be quite short, just the time the system reaches its equilibrium. Even when we wait hours, or rarely weeks, for thermodynamic equilibrium to be reached, it is not enough to explore the whole space of accessible micro-states. Why then is the result calculated with a probability distribution on this space identical to the observed result?

The principle of polls and the Monte Carlo method edit

The principle of polls may explain the equality between thermodynamic quantities actually measured and quantities calculated with statistical ensembles that have no physical reality. An average calculated on a representative sample can be an excellent approximation of the average calculated over the whole set, provided that the sample is sufficiently numerous and truly representative. During a thermodynamic measurement, the system only explores a small part of its accessible micro-states space, but it may be sufficiently large and representative for the measured quantity to be identical to that calculated with a statistical set. .

A thermodynamic measurement is similar to the Monte Carlo method. To evaluate an average, we calculate from a sample chosen at random. Theorists use the pseudo-random generators of computers to choose their samples. Experimenters trust Nature. It is like a random generator that chooses at each observation a representative sample that confirms our theoretical predictions. The Monte Carlo method is closer to physical reality than the statistical ensembles it serves to study. When one makes a thermodynamic measurement Nature itself applies the Monte Carlo method before providing us with the result.

That a brief temporal average is representative of the space of all accessible micro-states is a priori not at all obvious, and even rather excluded, because we observe only a small part of the trajectory of the system and it can be very different from other parts. How is it that Nature is a reliable random generator that gives us truly representative samples of very long-time averages?

Quantum decoherence edit

Thermodynamic laws must be justified from quantum physics, like all other physical laws, because quantum theory is the most fundamental physics. One can then wonder if the probabilities of the statistical ensembles can be interpreted as quantum probabilities. The theory of decoherence suggests it. If we observe a system that interacts with an environment that we do not observe, we must describe it with a density operator that defines a distribution of probabilities on the states of the system. Even if the initial state is precisely determined, the subsequent evolution is described by a probability distribution. This decoherence effect can be very fast. But the distributions of probabilities obtained by decoherence are not the distributions of the statistical ensembles of thermodynamics. Decoherence alone is not enough to solve the problem of short-time averages, but it can help to solve it, because it is a very fast, very powerful and very general effect that introduces a lot of randomness into the evolution of physical systems.

Microscopic entropy edit

Probability distributions computed by statistical physics (Maxwell-Boltzmann, Fermi-Dirac, Bose-Einstein) determine the probabilities of the states of the microscopic constituents of a thermodynamic system. These probabilities, which determine the velocities of a molecule in a gas, or quantum state occupation numbers, make it possible to define a microscopic entropy, i.e. an entropy per molecule, or per particle quantum state. The entropy of the whole system is the sum of the microscopic entropies of its constituents, provided that they are statistically independent (see complement). To take into account the indiscernibility of particles one must reason on quantum state occupation numbers.

The reality of microscopic entropy is not incompatible with the brevity of observations because the space of accessible states of a microscopic constituent is small. This is enough to justify the reality of microscopic entropy and from there the macroscopic entropy too. But for that we need to justify the statistical independence of the microscopic constituents.

The independence of microscopic constituents edit

The microscopic constituents of a system in thermodynamic equilibrium can not be perfectly independent. In order for them to be, they should not interact with each other at all. But if they do not interact, they can not exchange energy and thermal equilibrium is excluded.

For a thermodynamic equilibrium to be established, it is sufficient to assume that the constituents interact weakly with each other in a very diversified manner, that each constituent weakly interacts with a large number of other constituents. For example a molecule of a gas is weakly coupled to all the others, because they can collide, but it is a weak coupling because the probability of a particular collision is very small.

A microscopic constituent can have only a very small effect on its environment because it is very small compared to it. If furthermore this effect is diluted on many other parts, the possibility of a reaction of the environment to the effect of this constituent is negligible. Everything happens as if the environment remained statistically always almost the same, whatever the state of the microscopic constituent. The state of a constituent is therefore statistically almost independent of the state of its environment. Since this is true for all microscopic constituents, they are all almost independent of each other. It can be concluded that macroscopic entropy is the sum of microscopic entropy.

To justify the reality of statistical entropy, ergodic theory is not enough, it is necessary above all to prove the quasi-statistical independence of the microscopic constituents.

Lack of information, laisser-faire and equilibrium edit

The lack of information on the actual state of a thermodynamic system does not come from the laziness or incompetence of the observer but from the nature of the observed phenomena. Thermodynamic experiments let the observed systems reach or approach an equilibrium. We control only a small number of macroscopic quantities and we let the equilibrium settle by ignoring the micro-states. If we tried to know them more precisely, we could prevent the system from approaching equilibrium and we could not observe precisely what we want to observe, the equilibrium or the proximity of equilibrium. Letting the system roam randomly in its space of micro-states is a necessary condition for a thermodynamic equilibrium. Paradoxically, ignorance of micro-states, which is a subjective property of the observer, is a necessary condition for a thermodynamic equilibrium to occur, a real, objective event. This is why entropy, which measures a lack of information, is an objective material property. It is the lack of information that makes possible the thermodynamic equilibrium actually observed.

Information as fuel edit

Maxwell's demon edit

A Maxwell's demon shows that information can be transformed into work:

Consider a gas in a container. A partition is placed in the middle. It is equipped with a small door controlled by a device that detects the speed of the incident molecules. It opens the door only if a molecule that comes from the left goes faster than average or if a molecule that comes from the right goes slower than average. In this way the right compartment is warmed while the leeft one is cooled (Maxwell 1871). This difference in temperature can be used to operate a heat engine.

The door opener is a Maxwell's demon. It acquires information that can be transformed into work. Information is therefore a kind of fuel.

Maxwell invented his "demon" to show that the law entropy non-decrease is only a statistical truth that could be transgressed if one were able to modify the statistical equilibrium of the microscopic constituents. In its time, the existence of atoms and molecules was still very hypothetical. To consider the possibility of manipulating them was therefore out of the question. But as soon as the microscopic constituents of matter were better known, the possibility of a mechanical device that functions like a Maxwell's demon could be taken seriously.

To date, our ability to observe and manipulate microscopic constituents does not allow the device imagined by Maxwell to be realized, but scanning tunneling microscopy makes it possible to observe and manipulate atoms. One can then imagine a device that allows to recover work after reducing the entropy of the observed system, so a sort of theoretically feasible Maxwell's demon:

Consider a crystal that can accommodate atoms on its surface. It is assumed that initially   atoms are randomly distributed on   sites and that the temperature is low enough that they stay there. It is therefore a frozen disorder. We begin by observing the exact configuration of the surface atoms, which can be done with a scanning tunneling microscope, then we move them and collect them with the same microscope on a fraction   of the surface. The activity of the microscope resembles an isothermal compression work on a gas, except that it is not a gas but a frozen disorder on the surface.

Initially the number of possible configurations is equal to the number   of ways to place   atoms on   sites . The frozen disorder of the atoms on the surface thus brings a contribution   to the thermodynamic entropy of the crystal:

 

where we used Stirling's approximation:  

After ordering all the atoms  .

The law of entropy non-decrease seems thus transgressed, as Maxwell had predicted it, because we can manipulate atoms.

In principle, the displacement of atoms does not require any work because the work of tearing an atom can be recovered during redeposition. But since a scanning tunneling microscope consumes energy and dissipates heat, it does not diminish the total thermodynamic entropy. This objection is discussed below.

Amount of information and work edit

To convert the reduction of the thermodynamic entropy of the crystal into work, we put its surface in contact with an empty container of volume   whose other walls can not accommodate the atoms. This container is divided with a movable wall into two parts left and right whose volumes are respectively   and  . The crystal is heated to vaporize the atoms in the volume  . The resulting gas is then allowed to relax isothermally throughout the container, providing a work  . The crystal is then cooled to allow the atoms to redeposit on the surface of the crystal. If one proceeds reversibly, with a succession of thermal baths, the heat supplied during the heating by each thermal bath used is exactly equal to the heat it recovers during the cooling, because the specific heat at constant volume of a gas does not depend on its volume. The crystal and the thermal baths that were used to warm it have returned to their original state.

It has been supposed that an absorbing wall can make a perfect vacuum in an arbitrarily large volume. Such a wall can not exist otherwise one could make a perpetual motion of the second kind: the wall charged with atoms is placed in contact with an empty container, it is heated to a temperature sufficiently hot that all atoms are vaporised. The gas is then allowed to relax isothermally to provide work. The gas is then cooled to a temperature sufficiently cold that all atoms redeposit on the absorbing wall. If one proceeds reversibly the heat supplied during heating by each thermal bath is exactly equal to the heat it recovers during cooling. We could therefore return to the initial state after providing work by extracting heat from a single heat bath.

In order to make an exact calculation that is compatible with the laws of thermodynamics, it is necessary to take into account the equilibrium density of a gas in contact with an absorbing wall. This density can not be zero, but it can be very small, a priori as small as one wants if the wall is sufficiently absorbent. This is enough to justify the calculation above where this density is neglected.

Suppose  . So

 

If in addition  , we obtain

 

Now   is equal to the reduction of information entropy obtained when one observes the positions of all surface atoms. An example of the following theorem is thus obtained:

If information entropy is smaller than thermodynamic entropy, then the difference multiplied by the temperature   measures the maximum of the amount of work that the system can provide when it can receive heat only from a thermal bath at the temperature  .

This theorem was first established by Szilard in 1929. But his model is very unrealistic because it postulates that a single molecule can push a piston as if it were an ordinary gas.

Why can not Maxwell's demon reduce total entropy? edit

For the existence of a Maxwell's demon to be compatible with the laws of thermodynamics, at least one of the following conditions must be satisfied:

  1. The operation of the device does not reduce the entropy of the observed system because it increases it before decreasing it.
  2. The operation of the device increases the entropy of the environment.
  3. The operation of the device increases its own entropy.

Maxwell supposed that his demon had to see the molecules. But to see them one has to light the gas and thus warm it up. Such warming increases the entropy of the gas and one can expect this increase to be greater than the decrease caused by the establishment of a difference in temperature. In this case it is condition 1 that prevents the reduction of the total entropy.

Tunneling microscopy does not require light and really reduces the entropy of the observed system. But it consumes energy and gives heat to the environment. One is tempted to conclude that the acquisition of microscopic information prevents a Maxwell's demon from reducing total entropy because it has an energy cost. But the acquisition of information does not necessarily have an energy cost. If the complete system consisting of a detector and an observed system is perfectly isolated from its environment, this does not prevent the detector from acquiring information. During an ideal quantum measurement, for example, the complete system is isolated. If the observed system is in an eigenstate of measurement, and if there are n such possible initial states, there are also n possible final states of the detector, and the observed system is not disturbed. Initially, there are n possible initial states of the complete system, because the detector is in a single microstate. Finally there are also n possible final states of the complete system because the observed system and the detector are perfectly correlated. The information is therefore acquired without increasing the entropy of the complete system.

Physics does not prohibit the existence of a system capable of detecting atoms without energy costs.

Must we conclude that a Maxwell's demon can reduce total entropy?

Complements edit

The perpetual motion of the second kind edit

A machine that could lift a weight or move a car without being supplied with energy could make a perpetual motion of the first kind. The law of conservation of energy, the first law of thermodynamics, forbids the existence of such a machine. It is one of the most fundamental laws of physics. All physicists would be wrong if we could invent such a machine, but no one has ever invented it.

Perpetual movement of the second kind does not contradict the law of conservation of energy. Any body can yield energy if it is cooled, unless it is at zero temperature, equal to 0 Kelvin = -273.15 °Celsius = -459.67 °Fahrenheit. So we can imagine a car, a boat or a plane that could advance without consuming fuel. It would only have to absorb air or water at room temperature and reject it at a colder temperature. The difference in energy would be used to run the engine.

For such an engine to work it would be necessary to be able to separate a system whose temperature is uniform in two parts, one warmer, the other colder. But it is forbidden by the second law of thermodynamics because it would reduce total entropy. The impossibility of the perpetual motion of the second kind thus results from the law of non-decrease of the total entropy, the second law of thermodynamics.

Statistical entropy increase and the microcanonical distribution edit

The   are all accessible states of an almost isolated system, ie disturbances by the environment do not change the energy of the system.   is the transition probability per unit of time from the state   to the state  . It is assumed that all the microscopic evolutions are reversible :

 

for all   and all  .

  is the probability of the state   at the time  . By definition of  , we have:

 

 

since

 

Then

 

But

 

So

 

  and   are of the same sign and the   are always positive, therefore :

 

Paradoxically, the hypothesis of microscopic reversibility,  , leads to a law of irreversibility of macroscopic processes, since the entropy of a quasi-isolated system can never diminish.

The microcanonical distribution is an equilibrium distribution:

 

since   for all   and all  .

This is the only equilibrium distribution, because if the   are not all equal, there is at least one   smaller than the others. Of all the states   such that  , there is at least one for which   for a   such that  , otherwise they would not be accessible. Then

 

and the distribution is not in equilibrium.

The reality of entropy increase edit

The entropy non-decrease theorem is proved in a mathematically rigorous way for a statistical ensemble that has no real existence.   defines the occupation probability of the state   at the moment   for all the systems of a huge set imagined by theorists. It describes the evolution of this huge set, not the evolution of a real physical system. But under very general conditions, one can interpret the   as really measurable probabilities, and thus compare their evolution with the observed quantities.

It is assumed that the macroscopic evolution of the system is slow compared to microscopic fluctuations. The environment of each microscopic constituent is then almost constant over a sufficient period of time for it to explore its space of states and thus define probabilities of occupation of these states. For each microscopic constituent   one can thus define probabilities   of occupation of its states   and in principle measure them. Assuming that all microscopic constituents are statistically independent, these   are sufficient to define the probabilities   of all states   of the macroscopic system.

Frozen disorder and spontaneous decrease of accessibility entropy edit

During the liquid-glass transition, the total entropy of accessibility of the liquid and the thermal bath which cools it decreases. The decrease of accessibility entropy of the glass is not compensated by the increase of accessibility entropy of the thermal bath. It therefore seems that the theorem of increase of accessibility entropy is transgressed, while it is rigorously proven under very general conditions. But when the glass has frozen in a disordered configuration, the other configurations remain theoretically accessible. There is a negligible but non-zero probability that the thermal bath briefly gives up some of its heat which would allow the glass to be liquid again and then become glass again in another disordered configuration. All configurations are therefore in principle always accessible, but in practice the glass remains frozen in one. The theorem of increase of accessibility entropy considers that the space of accessible states does not change. It ignores the possibility that microstates become inaccessible in practice.

Entropy is an extensive quantity when the parts are statistically independent edit

The entropy of a sum is the sum of the entropies of the parts when they are independent:

Let   and   be two independent parts of the system  . The   and the   are the accessible states of   and   respectively.

The entropies of   and   are:

 

 

Accessible states of   are all states   for all   and all  . If   and   are independent the probability of   is   and the entropy of   is:

 

 

 

 

The Szilard's engine edit

To better understand the transformation of information into work, Szilard (1929) invited us to reason about an engine that works with a "one molecule gas":

A molecule is enclosed in a container that can be separated by a removable wall. When the wall is put in place in the middle of the container, the presence of the molecule in one or the other of the separate compartments is detected. So a bit of information is acquired. The wall is then used as a piston on which the molecule can work. It is necessary to know where the molecule is to know in which direction of piston displacement a work can be recovered. In this way it is calculated that under optimal conditions an bit of information is used to recover a work equal to  . This is the work done by a molecule on a piston during an isothermal expansion at the temperature   that doubles the accessible volume.

Szilard's engine seems to contradict thermodynamics because it suggests that we could make a perpetual motion of the second kind. If the piston can move in only one direction, it is not necessary to know the position of the molecule to recover work. Once in two the piston remains motionless because the molecule is on the wrong side of the piston, and we do not recover any work, but once in two it moves and we recover a work equal to  . By repeating the experiment many times we could thus obtain an arbitrary amount of work without spending any to know the position of the molecule.

But such a process requires a device that removes the piston and puts it back in place. Now there are two possible positions of the piston at the end of a cycle, either in the middle if it has not moved, or at one end, if it has moved. The device must therefore acquire a bit of information at the end of each cycle. To return to its initial state, it must erase this information. The cost of erasing information is thus here too at the origin of the impossibility of a perpetual motion of the second kind (Leff & Rex 1990).

Szilard's engine confirms that the entropy of accessibility can be different from the thermodynamic entropy: when we introduce a wall in the middle of the one molecule gas, the reduction of the entropy of accessibility is  . On the other hand, the thermodynamic entropy is not reduced since the gas does not yield heat. For the Szilard's engine, the entropy of accessibility can be reduced in principle as much as we want. We just have to place several walls inside the container.

Why does the entropy of the Universe increase? edit

The law of entropy increase suggests that the entropy of the Universe can only increase, that it started in a macrostate of low entropy, hot but very condensed, and that its expansion allowed it to cool down while increasing its entropy. But this statement faces two difficulties:

  • As the Universe is perfectly isolated its entropy, if we could define it, should be conserved.
  • It is not really meaningful to talk about the macrostate of the Universe, because there is no sense in talking about the space of its possible microstates. It is in a single microstate, sometimes called the wave function of the Universe.

But there is nevertheless a sense to say that the entropy of the Universe increases. We can assign entropy to its various parts (stars, planets, black holes, interstellar medium ...) and find that the sum of all these entropies increases. But when we do this, we suppose that the parts are statistically independent, we ignore their correlations. The ignorance of correlations leads to overestimate the total entropy. If we knew the microstate of the universe, we would also know all the correlations between its parts and we would note that the total entropy does not increase. It would always remain equal to zero. But knowing the microstate of the universe is obviously impossible.

References edit

Bennett, Charles H., The thermodynamics of computation - a review (Int. J. Theor. Phys. 21, 905-40, 1982, reproduced in Leff & Rex 1990)

Diu, Bernard, Guthmann, Claudine, Lederer, Danielle, Roulet, Bernard, Éléments de physique statistique (1989)

Feynman, Richard P., Lectures on computation (1996)

Landauer, Rolf W., Irreversibility and heat generation in the computing process (IBM J. Res. Dev. 5, 183-91, 1961, reproduced in Leff & Rex 1990)

Leff, Harvey S., Rex, Andrew F., Maxwell's demon, entropy, information, computing (1990)

Maxwell, James Clerk, Theory of heat (1871)

Sethna, James P., Statistical mechanics : entropy, order parameters and complexity (2018)

Szilard, Leo, On the decrease of entropy in a thermodynamic system by the intervention of intelligent beings (Zeitschrift für Physik, 1929, 53, 840-856, translated in Leff & Rex 1990)


Next chapter: Quantum theory of multiple destinies >>>