We have defined satisfaction in a model with a variable assignment. We have expressed formula
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
being satisfied by model
M
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
with variable assignment
s
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} \,\!}
as
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
φ
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \varphi \,\!}
Now we can also say that a formula
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
is satisfied by model
M
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
(not limited to a specific variable assignment) if
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
is satisfied by
M
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
with every variable assignment. Thus
M
⊨
φ
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\ \vDash \varphi \,\!}
if and only if
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
φ
for every
s
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \varphi \ {\mbox{for every}}\ \mathrm {s} \ .\,\!}
If no free variables occur in
φ
,
{\displaystyle \varphi ,\,\!}
(that is, if
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
is a sentence), then
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
is true in model
M
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
.
Variable assignments allow us to deal with free variables when doing the semantic analysis of a formula. For two variable assignments,
s
1
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s_{1}} \,\!}
and
s
2
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s_{2}} \,\!}
, satisfaction by
⟨
M
,
s
1
⟩
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s_{1}} \rangle \,\!}
differs from satisfaction by
⟨
M
,
s
2
⟩
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s_{2}} \rangle \,\!}
only if the formula has free variables. But sentences do not have free variables. Thus a model satisfies a sentence with at least one variable assignment if and only if it satisfies the sentence with every variable assignment. The following two definitions are equivalent:
A sentence
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
is true in
M
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
if and only if there is a variable assignment
s
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} \,\!}
such that
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
φ
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \varphi \ .\,\!}
A sentence
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
is true in
M
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
if and only if, for every variable assignment
s
,
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} ,\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
φ
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \varphi \ .\,\!}
The latter is just a notational variant of:
A sentence
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi \,\!}
is true in
M
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
if and only if
M
⊨
φ
.
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M}}\ \vDash \varphi \ .\,\!}
On the previous page , we looked at the following model and variable assignment.
For the model
I
M
:
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M}}\ :\,\!}
|
M
|
=
{
1
,
2
,
3
}
.
{\displaystyle |{\mathfrak {M}}|\ =\ \{1,\,2,\,3\}\ .\,\!}
I
M
(
a
0
0
)
=
0
.
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M}}(a_{0}^{0})\ =\ 0\ .\,\!}
I
M
(
b
0
0
)
=
1
.
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M}}(b_{0}^{0})\ =\ 1\ .\,\!}
I
M
(
c
0
0
)
=
2
.
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M}}(c_{0}^{0})\ =\ 2\ .\,\!}
I
M
(
f
0
2
)
=
f
0
2
such that:
f
0
2
(
0
,
0
)
=
2
,
f
0
2
(
0
,
1
)
=
1
,
f
0
2
(
0
,
2
)
=
0
,
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M}}(f_{0}^{2})\ =\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}\ {\mbox{such that:}}\quad {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(0,\,0)=2,\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(0,\,1)\ =\ 1,\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(0,\,2)=0,\,\!}
f
0
2
(
1
,
0
)
=
1
,
f
0
2
(
1
,
1
)
=
0
,
f
0
2
(
1
,
2
)
=
2
,
f
0
2
(
2
,
0
)
=
0
,
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(1,\,0)=1,\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(1,\,1)\ =\ 0,\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(1,\,2)=2,\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(2,\,0)=0,\,\!}
f
0
2
(
2
,
1
)
=
2
,
and
f
0
2
(
2
,
2
)
=
1
.
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(2,\,1)=2,\ {\mbox{and}}\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(2,\,2)=1\ .\,\!}
I
M
(
F
0
2
)
=
{
⟨
0
,
1
⟩
,
⟨
1
,
2
⟩
,
⟨
2
,
1
⟩
}
.
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F_{0}^{2}} )\ =\ \{\langle 0,\ 1\rangle ,\ \langle 1,\ 2\rangle ,\ \langle 2,\ 1\rangle \}\ .\,\!}
For the variable assignment
s
:
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} \ :\,\!}
s
(
x
0
)
=
0
.
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} (x_{0})\ =\ 0\ .\,\!}
s
(
y
0
)
=
1
.
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} (y_{0})\ =\ 1\ .\,\!}
s
(
z
0
)
=
2
.
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} (z_{0})\ =\ 2\ .\,\!}
We noted the following results:
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
F
(
a
,
b
)
,
F
(
b
,
c
)
,
and
F
(
c
,
b
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (a,b),\ \mathrm {F} (b,c),\ {\mbox{and}}\ \mathrm {F} (c,b)\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊭
F
(
a
,
a
)
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \not \vDash \mathrm {F} (a,a))\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
F
(
a
,
f
(
a
,
b
)
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (a,f(a,b))\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊭
F
(
f
(
a
,
b
)
,
a
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \not \vDash \mathrm {F} (f(a,b),a)\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
F
(
c
,
b
)
→
F
(
a
,
b
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (c,b)\rightarrow \mathrm {F} (a,b)\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊭
F
(
c
,
b
)
→
F
(
b
,
a
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \not \vDash \mathrm {F} (c,b)\rightarrow \mathrm {F} (b,a)\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊭
∀
x
∀
y
(
F
(
x
,
y
)
→
F
(
y
,
x
)
)
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \not \vDash \forall x\,\forall y\,(\mathrm {F} (x,y)\rightarrow \mathrm {F} (y,x))\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
∃
x
∃
y
(
F
(
x
,
y
)
∧
F
(
y
,
x
)
)
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \exists x\,\exists y\,(\mathrm {F} (x,y)\land \mathrm {F} (y,x))\,\!}
We also noted above that for sentences (though not for formulae in general), a model satisfies the sentence with at least one variable assignment if and only if it satisfies the sentence with every variable assignment. Thus the results just listed hold for every variable assignment, not just
s
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} \,\!}
.
Applying our definition of truth, we get:
(
1
)
F
(
a
,
b
)
,
F
(
b
,
c
)
,
and
F
(
c
,
b
)
are True in
M
.
{\displaystyle (1)\quad \mathrm {F} (a,b),\ \mathrm {F} (b,c),\ {\mbox{and}}\ \mathrm {F} (c,b)\ {\mbox{are True in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
(
2
)
F
(
a
,
a
)
is False in
M
.
{\displaystyle (2)\quad \mathrm {F} (a,a)\ {\mbox{is False in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
(
3
)
F
(
a
,
f
(
a
,
b
)
)
is True in
M
.
{\displaystyle (3)\quad \mathrm {F} (a,f(a,b))\ {\mbox{is True in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
(
4
)
F
(
f
(
a
,
b
)
,
a
)
is False in
M
.
{\displaystyle (4)\quad \mathrm {F} (f(a,b),a)\ {\mbox{is False in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
(
5
)
F
(
c
,
b
)
→
F
(
a
,
b
)
is True in
M
.
{\displaystyle (5)\quad \mathrm {F} (c,b)\rightarrow \mathrm {F} (a,b)\ {\mbox{is True in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
(
6
)
F
(
c
,
b
)
→
F
(
b
,
a
)
is False in
M
.
{\displaystyle (6)\quad \mathrm {F} (c,b)\rightarrow \mathrm {F} (b,a)\ {\mbox{is False in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
(
7
)
∀
x
∀
y
(
F
(
x
,
y
)
→
F
(
y
,
x
)
)
is false in
M
.
{\displaystyle (7)\quad \forall x\,\forall y\,(\mathrm {F} (x,y)\rightarrow \mathrm {F} (y,x))\ {\mbox{is false in }}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
(
8
)
∃
x
∃
y
(
F
(
x
,
y
)
∧
F
(
y
,
x
)
)
is true in
M
.
{\displaystyle (8)\quad \exists x\,\exists y\,(\mathrm {F} (x,y)\land \mathrm {F} (y,x))\ {\mbox{is true in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}\ .\,\!}
This corresponds to the goals (1)–(8) of the previous page . We have now achieved those goals.
On Models page , we also considered an infinite model
I
M
2
:
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M_{2}}}\ :\,\!}
|
M
2
|
=
{
0
,
1
,
2
,
.
.
.
}
{\displaystyle |{\mathfrak {M}}_{2}|=\{0,1,2,...\}\,\!}
I
M
2
(
a
0
0
)
=
0
.
{\displaystyle I_{{\mathfrak {M}}_{2}}(a_{0}^{0})\ =\ 0\ .\,\!}
I
M
2
(
b
0
0
)
=
1
.
{\displaystyle I_{{\mathfrak {M}}_{2}}(b_{0}^{0})\ =\ 1\ .\,\!}
I
M
2
(
c
0
0
)
=
2
.
{\displaystyle I_{{\mathfrak {M}}_{2}}(c_{0}^{0})\ =\ 2\ .\,\!}
I
M
2
(
f
0
2
)
=
f
0
2
such that
f
0
2
(
u
,
v
)
=
u
+
v
.
{\displaystyle I_{{\mathfrak {M}}_{2}}(f_{0}^{2})\ =\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}\ {\mbox{such that}}\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(u,v)=u+v\ .\,\!}
I
M
2
(
F
0
2
)
=
{
⟨
x
,
y
⟩
:
x
<
y
}
.
{\displaystyle I_{{\mathfrak {M}}_{2}}(\mathrm {F_{0}^{2}} )\ =\ \{\langle x,\ y\rangle :\ x<y\}\ .\,\!}
We can reuse the same variable assignment from above, namely
s
:
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} \ :\,\!}
s
(
x
0
)
=
0
.
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} (x_{0})\ =\ 0\ .\,\!}
s
(
y
0
)
=
1
.
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} (y_{0})\ =\ 1\ .\,\!}
s
(
z
0
)
=
2
.
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} (z_{0})\ =\ 2\ .\,\!}
Example of extended variable assignment
edit
On the Models page , we listed the following goals for our definitions.
f
(
a
,
b
)
resolves to
1
i
n
M
2
.
{\displaystyle f(a,b)\ {\mbox{resolves to}}\ 1\ \mathrm {in} \ {\mathfrak {M}}_{2}\ .\,\!}
This does not require our definition of truth or the definition of satisfaction; it is simply requires evaluating the exended variable assignment. We have for any
s
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} \,\!}
on defined on
I
M
{\displaystyle I_{\mathfrak {M}}\,\!}
:
s
¯
(
f
(
a
,
b
)
)
=
I
M
(
f
)
(
s
¯
(
a
)
,
s
¯
(
b
)
)
=
f
0
2
(
s
¯
(
a
)
,
s
¯
(
b
)
)
{\displaystyle {\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(f(a,b))\ =\ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(f)\,(\ {\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(a),\,{\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(b)\ )\ =\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(\ {\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(a),\,{\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(b)\ )\,\!}
=
f
0
2
(
I
M
(
a
)
,
I
M
(
b
)
)
=
f
0
2
(
0
,
1
)
{\displaystyle =\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(\ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(a),\,I_{\mathfrak {M}}(b)\ )\ =\ {\mathfrak {f}}_{0}^{2}(0,\,1)\,\!}
=
0
+
1
=
1
.
{\displaystyle =\ 0+1\ =\ 1\ .\,\!}
Example results without quantifiers
edit
We also listed the following goal on the Models page .
(
9
)
F
(
a
,
b
)
and
F
(
b
,
c
)
are True in
M
2
.
{\displaystyle (9)\quad \mathrm {F} (a,b)\ {\mbox{and}}\ \mathrm {F} (b,c)\ {\mbox{are True in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}_{2}\ .\,\!}
(
10
)
F
(
c
,
b
)
and
F
(
a
,
a
)
are False in
M
2
.
{\displaystyle (10)\quad \mathrm {F} (c,b)\ {\mbox{and}}\ \mathrm {F} (a,a)\ {\mbox{are False in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}_{2}\ .\,\!}
First we note that:
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
F
(
a
,
b
)
because
⟨
s
¯
(
a
)
,
s
¯
(
b
)
⟩
=
⟨
0
,
1
⟩
∈
I
M
(
F
)
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (a,b)\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \langle {\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(a),\,{\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(b)\rangle \ =\ \langle 0,\,1\rangle \ \in \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\ \,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊨
F
(
b
,
c
)
because
⟨
s
¯
(
b
)
,
s
¯
(
c
)
⟩
=
⟨
1
,
2
⟩
∈
I
M
(
F
)
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (b,c)\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \langle {\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(b),\,{\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(c)\rangle \ =\ \langle 1,\,2\rangle \ \in \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊭
F
(
c
,
b
)
because
⟨
s
¯
(
c
)
,
s
¯
(
b
)
⟩
=
⟨
2
,
1
⟩
∉
I
M
(
F
)
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \not \vDash \mathrm {F} (c,b)\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \langle {\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(c),\,{\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(b)\rangle \ =\ \langle 2,\,1\rangle \ \notin \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\,\!}
⟨
M
,
s
⟩
⊭
F
(
a
,
a
)
because
⟨
s
¯
(
a
)
,
s
¯
(
a
)
⟩
=
⟨
0
,
0
⟩
∉
I
M
(
F
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \not \vDash \mathrm {F} (a,a)\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \langle {\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(a),\,{\overline {\mathrm {s} }}(a)\rangle \ =\ \langle 0,\,0\rangle \ \notin \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\ .\,\!}
Indeed:
⟨
0
,
1
⟩
∈
I
M
(
F
)
because
0
<
1
{\displaystyle \langle 0,\,1\rangle \ \in \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \ 0<1\,\!}
⟨
1
,
2
⟩
∈
I
M
(
F
)
because
1
<
2
{\displaystyle \langle 1,\,2\rangle \ \in \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \ 1<2\,\!}
⟨
2
,
1
⟩
∉
I
M
(
F
)
because
2
≮
1
{\displaystyle \langle 2,\,1\rangle \ \notin \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \ 2\not <1\,\!}
⟨
0
,
0
⟩
∉
I
M
(
F
)
because
0
≮
0
.
{\displaystyle \langle 0,\,0\rangle \ \notin \ I_{\mathfrak {M}}(\mathrm {F} )\ \ {\mbox{because}}\ \ 0\not <0\ .\,\!}
Because the formulae of (9) and (10) are sentences,
⟨
M
⟩
⊨
F
(
a
,
b
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}}\rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (a,b)\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
⟩
⊨
F
(
b
,
c
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}}\rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (b,c)\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
⟩
⊭
F
(
c
,
b
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}}\rangle \ \not \vDash \mathrm {F} (c,b)\ .\,\!}
⟨
M
⟩
⊭
F
(
a
,
a
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M}}\rangle \ \not \vDash \mathrm {F} (a,a)\ .\,\!}
Applying the definition of truth, we find the goals of (9) and (10) achieved. The sentences of (9) are true and those of (10) are false.
Example results with quantifiers
edit
In addition, we listed the following goal on the Models page .
(
11
)
∀
x
∃
y
F
(
x
,
y
)
is true in
M
2
.
{\displaystyle (11)\quad \forall x\,\exists y\,\mathrm {F} (x,y)\ {\mbox{is true in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}_{2}\ .\,\!}
(
12
)
∀
x
∃
y
F
(
y
,
x
)
is false in
M
2
.
{\displaystyle (12)\quad \forall x\,\exists y\,\mathrm {F} (y,x)\ {\mbox{is false in}}\ {\mathfrak {M}}_{2}\ .\,\!}
Corresponding to (11):
(
13
)
⟨
M
2
,
s
⟩
⊨
∀
x
∃
y
F
(
x
,
y
)
{\displaystyle (13)\quad \langle {\mathfrak {M_{2}}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \forall x\,\exists y\,\mathrm {F} (x,y)\,\!}
is true if and only if, for each i a member of the domain, the following is true of at least one j a member of the domain:
⟨
M
2
,
s
[
x
:
i
,
x
:
j
]
⟩
⊨
F
(
x
,
y
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M_{2}}},\ \mathrm {s} [x\!:\,i,x\!:\,j]\rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (x,y)\ .\,\!}
But
F
0
2
{\displaystyle \mathrm {F_{0}^{2}} \,\!}
was assigned the less then relation. Thus the preceding holds if and only if, for every member of the domain, there is a larger member of the domain. Given that the domain is
{
0
,
1
,
2
,
.
.
.
}
,
{\displaystyle \{0,1,2,...\},\,\!}
this is obviously true. Thus, (13) is true. Given that the formula of (11) and (12) is a sentence, we find the goal expressed as (11) to be met.
Corresponding to (12):
(
14
)
⟨
M
2
,
s
⟩
⊨
∀
x
∃
y
F
(
y
,
x
)
{\displaystyle (14)\quad \langle {\mathfrak {M_{2}}},\ \mathrm {s} \rangle \ \vDash \forall x\,\exists y\,\mathrm {F} (y,x)\,\!}
is true if and only if, for each i a member of the domain, the following is true of at least one j a member of the domain:
⟨
M
2
,
s
[
x
:
i
,
x
:
j
]
⟩
⊨
F
(
y
,
x
)
.
{\displaystyle \langle {\mathfrak {M_{2}}},\ \mathrm {s} [x\!:\,i,x\!:\,j]\rangle \ \vDash \mathrm {F} (y,x)\ .\,\!}
This holds if and only if, for every member of the domain, there is a smaller member of the domain. But there is no member of the domain smaller than 0. Thus (14) is false. The formula of (12) and (14) fails to be satisfied by
M
2
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M_{2}}}\,\!}
with variable assignment
s
{\displaystyle \mathrm {s} \,\!}
. The formula of (12) and (14) is a sentence, so it fails to be satisfied by
M
2
{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {M_{2}}}\,\!}
with any variable assignment. The formula (a sentence) of (12) and (14) is false, and so the goal of (12) is met.