Finite Model Theory/Preliminaries

First Order Logic (FO)

edit

We only give a very rough summary of FO here. An introduction can be found at FO.

Syntax

edit

Syntax is 'just' about sequences of signs. The alphabet of FO consists of:

  • Variables  
  • Logical Connectives:  ,  
  • Quantifiers:  
  • Equality:  
  • Parenthesis: ), (
  • n-ary Relation symbols, for no or many n>0, e.g. R(., .)
  • Constant symbols (none or many)

The handling of parenthesis is done the 'usual' way and is not formally described further.

For a given set of symbols S, variables and constant symbols are said to be S-Terms.

S-Expressions are obtained by the multiple application of the following rules:

  •   is an expression
  •   is an expression, for an n-ary relation symbol R
  •   are expressions
  •   is an expression

where   is a term and   an expression.

So additional connectives for OR, IMPLICATION, EQUIVALENCE etc. can be defined as well as the FOR ALL quantifier.

Semantics

edit

Semantics adds the meaning to the language in three steps:

  • 1st it defines what the logical symbols (connectives and quantifiers) mean (this always holds in FO),
  • 2nd it maps relation symbols and constant symbols to actual relations and constants over a given set of entities (this is usually defined per subject, like Analysis or Statistics) and
  • 3rd it maps free variables (not bound to a quantifier) to entities (usually done per Problem, like solving an equation).

1st we assume the Logical Symbols   to have the usual meaning.

2nd a S-Structure is a pair (A, a) of

  • a nonempty set A, the Universe, and
  • a mapping a from S, such that
    • each n-ary relation symbol is mapped to a n-ary relation on A and
    • each constant symbol is mapped to an element of A

3rd an Interpretation is a pair   where   = (A, a) is a S-Structure and   is a mapping from all free variables to an element of A.

An Interpretation is said to be a Model of a set   of S-expressions ( ) iff all of the following hold

  •  , for  
  •   , for  
  • Not   , for  
  •   and  , for  
  • It exists an   s.t.  , for  

Game

edit

A game is described by

  • its players (>1),
  • its rules i.e. who plays when and what is allowed to do and
  • its possible ends and payoffs.

More formal, it's a tuple (P, T, m, u) where

  • P (the Players) is a set, with |P| = n > 1
  • is a graph on a set of nodes that forms a taxonomy, i.e. a T is a tree with a dedicated root node. The leafs called terminal nodes T all others decision nodes D. This describes the possible move sequences.
  • m is a mapping from D to P, that says who is to move at what point.
  • u is a set of mappings ui (one for each player i) from T to an ordered set U, that give the payoff for a player at each terminal node.

We assume here and in the following that every player has perfect information (so the above definition is incomplete), i.e. all moves of all players made so far, and we don't consider move by chance. Common knowledge about the rules and players is assumed anyway. The above is called the extensive form representation of a game. Others like the normal form reptresentation make simplifying assumptions on this (e.g. about the information) and use the concept of strategy instead of single moves.

Notice that different moves can lead to the same 'position', i.e. a position can be represented more than once in a game-tree. And, the same payoffs can have different meanings to different players.

Isomorphism on Structures

edit

Homomorphism

edit

Isomorphism

edit

Back and Forth Method

edit

Counting a set can get messy due to

  • counting things in an other than the natural order
  • counting elements multiple times

...

Method

edit

Fix enumerations (without repetition) of the underlying sets:

 

Now we construct a one-to-one correspondence between A and B that is strictly increasing. Initially no member of A is paired with any member of B.

(1) Let i be the smallest index such that ai is not yet paired with any member of B. Let j be the smallest index such that bj is not yet paired with any member of A and ai can be paired with bj consistently with the requirement that the pairing be strictly increasing. Pair ai with bj.
(2) Let j be the smallest index such that bj is not yet paired with any member of A. Let i be the smallest index such that ai is not yet paired with any member of B and bj can be paired with ai consistently with the requirement that the pairing be strictly increasing. Pair bj with ai.
(3) Go back to step (1).

It still has to be checked that the choice required in step (1) and (2) can actually be made in accordance to the requirements. Using step (1) as an example:

If there are already ap and aq in A corresponding to bp and bq in B respectively such that   and  , we choose bj in between bp and bq using density. Otherwise, we choose a suitable large or small element of B using the fact that B has neither a maximum nor a minimum. Choices made in step (2) are dually possible. Finally, the construction ends after countably many steps because A and B are countably infinite. Note that we had to use all the prerequisites.

If we iterated only step (1), rather than going back and forth, then the resulting pairing would fail to be bijective.