Commutative Algebra/Primary decomposition or Lasker–Noether theory

The following theory was originally developed by world chess champion Emmanuel Lasker in his 1905 paper "Zur theorie der Moduln und Ideale" ("On the theory of modules and ideals") on polynomial rings, and then generalised by Emmy Noether to commutative rings satisfying the ascending chain condition (noetherian rings), in her revolutionary 1921 paper "Idealtheorie in Ringbereichen".

Primary ideals

edit

Definition 19.4:

An ideal   is called primary ideal if and only if the following holds:

 .

Clearly, every prime ideal is primary.

We have the following characterisations:

Theorem 19.5 (characterisations of primary ideals):

Let  , with   denoting the radical ideal of  . The following are equivalent:

  1.   is primary.
  2. If  , then either   or   or  .
  3. Every zerodivisor of   is nilpotent.

Proof 1:

1.   2.: Let   be primary. Assume   and neither   nor  . Since  ,   for a suitable  . Since   and  ,   for a suitable  .

2.   3.: Let   be a zerodivisor of  , that is,   for a certain   such that  . Hence  , that is,   for a suitable  .

3.   1.: Let  . Then either   or   or   is a zerodivisor within  , which is why   for a suitable  . 

Proof 2:

1.   3.: Let   be primary, and let   be a zerodivisor within  . Then   for a   and hence   for a suitable  .

3.   2.: Let  . Assume neither   nor  . Then both   and   are zerodivisors in  , and hence are nilpotent, which is why   for suitable   and hence  .

2.   1.: Let  . Assume not   and not  . Then in particular  , that is,   for suitable  . 

Theorem 19.6:

If   is any primary ideal, then   is prime.

Proof:

Let  . Then   for a suitable  . Hence either   and thus   or   for a suitable   and hence  . 

Existence

edit

Existence in the Noetherian case

edit

Following the exposition of Zariski, Samuel and Cohen, we deduce the classical Noetherian existence theorem from two lemmas and a definition.

Definition 19.7:

An ideal   is called irreducible if and only if it can not be written as the intersection of finitely many proper superideals.

Lemma 19.8:

In a Noetherian ring, every irreducible ideal is primary.

Proof:

Assume there exists an irreducible ideal   which is not primary. Since   is not primary, there exist   such that  , but neither   nor   for any  . We form the ascending chain of ideals

 ;

this chain is ascending because  . Since we are in a Noetherian ring, this chain eventually stabilizes at some  ; that is, for   we have  . We now claim that

 .

Indeed,   is obvious, and for   we note that if  , then

 

for suitable   and  , which is why  , hence  , since   thus  ,  , hence   and  . Therefore  .

Furthermore, by the choice of   and   both   and   are proper superideals, contradicting the irreducibility of  . 

Lemma 19.9:

In a Noetherian ring, every ideal can be written as the finite intersection of irreducible ideals.

Proof:

Assume otherwise. Consider the set of all ideals that are not the finite intersection of irreducible ideals. If we are given an ascending chain within that set

 ,

this chain has an upper bound, since it stabilizes as we are in a Noetherian ring. We may hence choose a maximal element   among all ideals that are not the finite intersection of irreducible ideals.   itself is thus not irreducible. Hence, it can be written as the intersection of strict superideals; that is

 

for appropriate  . Since   is maximal, each   is a finite intersection of irreducible ideals, and hence so is  , which contradicts the choice of  . 

Corollary 19.10:

In a Noetherian ring, every ideal can be written as the finite intersection of primary ideals.

Proof:

Combine lemmas 19.8 and 19.9. 

Minimal decomposition

edit

Definition 19.11:

Let   be an ideal in a ring, and let

 

be a primary decomposition of  . This decomposition is called minimal if and only if

  1. there does not exist   with  , and
  2. for all  ,   (that is, the radicals of the prime ideals are pairwise distinct).

In fact, once we have a primary composition for a given ideal, we can find a minimal primary decomposition of that ideal. But before we prove that, we need a general fact about radicals first.

Lemma 19.12:

Let   be ideals. Then

 .

One could phrase this lemma as "radical interchanges with finite intersections".

Proof:

 :

 

 : Let  . For each  , choose   such that  . Set

 .

Then  , hence  . 

  Note that for infinite intersections, the lemma need not (!!!) be true.

Theorem 19.13:

Let   be an ideal in a ring that has a primary decomposition. Then   also has a minimal primary decomposition.

Proof 1:

First of all, we may exclude all primary ideals   for which

 ;

the intersection won't change if we do that, for intersecting with a superset changes nothing in general.

Then assume we are given a decomposition

 ,

and for a fixed prime ideal   set

 ;

due to theorem 19.6,

 .

We claim that   is primary, and  . For the first claim, note that by the previous lemma

 .

For the second claim, let  . If   there is nothing to prove. Otherwise let  . Then there exists   such that  , and hence   for a suitable  . Thus  , and hence   for all   and suitable  . Pick

 .

Then  . Hence,   is primary. 

Uniqueness properties

edit

In general, we don't have uniqueness for primary decompositions, but still, any two primary decompositions of the same ideal in a ring look somewhat similar. The classical first and second uniqueness theorems uncover some of these similarities.

Theorem 19.14 (first uniqueness theorem):

Let   be an ideal within a ring  , and assume we are given a minimal primary decomposition

 .

Then the prime (theorem 19.6) ideals   are exactly the prime ideals among the ideals   and hence are independent of the choice of the particular decomposition. That is, the ideals   are uniquely determined by  .

Proof:

We begin by deducing an equation. According to theorem 19.2 and lemma 19.12,

 .

Now we fix   and distinguish a few cases.

  1. If  , then obviously  .
  2. If   (where again  ), then if   we must have   since no power of   is contained within  .
  3. If  , but  , we have  , since
     

In conclusion, we find

 .

Assume first that   is prime. Then the prime avoidance lemma implies that   is contained within one of the  ,  , and since  ,  .

Let now   for   be given. Since the given primary decomposition is minimal, we find   such that  , but  . In this case,   by the above equation. 

This theorem motivates and enables the following definition:

Definition 19.15:

Let   be any ideal that has a minimal primary decomposition

 .

Then the ideals   are called the prime ideals belonging to  .

We now prove two lemmas, each of which will below yield a proof of the second uniqueness theorem (see below).

Lemma 19.16:

Let   be an ideal which has a primary decomposition

 ,

and let again   for all  . If we define

 ,

then   is an ideal of   and  .

Proof:

Let  . There exists   such that   without  , and a similar   with an analogous property in regard to  . Hence  , but not   since   is prime. Also,  . Hence, we have an ideal.

Let  . There exists   such that

 .

In particular,  . Since no power of   is in  ,  . 

Lemma 19.17:

Let   be multiplicatively closed, and let

 

be the canonical morphism. Let   be a decomposable ideal, that is

 

for primary  , and number the   such that the first     have empty intersection with  , and the others nonempty intersection. Then

 .

Proof:

We have

 

by theorem 9.?. If now  , lemma 9.? yields  . Hence,

 .

Application of   on both sides yields

 ,

and

 

since   holds for general maps, and   means  , where   and  ; thus  , that is  . This means that

 .

Hence  , and since no power of   is in   (  is multiplicatively closed and  ),  . 

Definition 19.18:

Let   be an ideal which admits a primary decomposition, and let   be a set of prime ideals of   that all belong to  .   is called isolated if and only if for every prime ideal  , if   is a prime ideal belonging to   such that  , then   as well.

Theorem 19.19 (second uniqueness theorem):

Let   be an ideal that has a minimal primary decomposition. If   is a subset of the set of the prime ideals belonging to   which is isolated, then

 

is independent of the particular minimal primary decomposition from which the   are coming.

Note that applied to reduced sets consisting of only one prime ideal, this means that if all prime subideals of a prime ideal   belonging to   also belong to  , then the corresponding   is predetermined.

Proof 1 (using lemma 19.16):

We first reduce the theorem down to the case where   is the set of all prime subideals belonging to   of a prime ideal that belongs to  . Let   be any reduced system. For each maximal element of that set   (w.r.t. inclusion) define   to be the set of all ideals in   contained in  . Since   is finite,

 ;

this need not be a disjoint union (note that these are not maximal ideals!). Hence

 .

Hence, let   be an ideal belonging to   and let   be an isolated system of subideals of  . Let   be all the primary ideals belonging to   not in  . For those ideals, we have  , and hence we find  . For each   take   large enough so that  . Then

 ,

which is why  . From this follows that

 ,

where   is the element in the primary decomposition of   to which   is associated, since clearly for each element   of the left hand side,   and thus  , but also  . But on the other hand,   implies  . Hence for any such   lemma 19.16 implies

 ,

which in turn implies

 . 

Proof 2 (using lemma 19.17):

Let   be an isolated system of prime ideals belonging to  . Pick

 ,

which is multiplicatively closed since it's the intersection of multiplicatively closed subsets. The primary ideals of the decomposition of   which correspond to the   are precisely those having empty intersection with  , since any other primary ideal   in the decomposition of   must contain an element outside all  , since otherwise its radical would be one of them by isolatedness. Hence, lemma 19.17 gives

 

and we have independence of the particular decomposition. 

Characterisation of prime ideals belonging to an ideal

edit

The following are useful further theorems on primary decomposition.

First of all, we give a proposition on general prime ideals.

Proposition 19.20:

Let   be a (commutative) ring, and let   be a prime ideal. If   contains

either the intersection   or the product  

of certain arbitrary ideals, then it contains one of the   completely.

Proof:

Since the product is contained in the intersection, it suffices to prove the theorem under the assumption that  .

Indeed, assume none of the   is contained in  . Choose   for  . Since   is prime,  . But it's in the product, contradiction. 

This proposition has far-reaching consequences for primary decomposition, given in Corollary 19.22. But first, we need a lemma.

Lemma 19.21:

Let   be a primary ideal, and assume   is prime such that  . Then  .

Proof:

If  , then  . 

Corollary 19.22:

Let   be an ideal admitting a prime decomposition

 .

If   is any prime ideal that contains  , then it also contains a prime ideal belonging to  . Further, the prime ideals belonging to   are exactly those that are minimal with respect to the partial order induced by inclusion on  .

Proof:

The first assertion follows from proposition 19.20 and lemma 19.21. The second assertion follows since any prime ideal belonging to   contains  .