Analytic Number Theory/Arithmetic functions

In this chapter, we shall set up the basic theory of arithmetic functions. This theory will be seen in action in later chapters, but in particular in chapter 9.

Definitions

edit

Definition 2.1:

An arithmetical function is a function  .

Definition 2.2 (important arithmetical functions):

  1. The Kronecker delta:  
  2. Euler's totient function:  
  3. Möbius'  -function:  
  4. The von Mangoldt function:  
  5. The monomials:  
  6. The number of distinct prime divisors:  ,  
  7. The sum of prime factors with multiplicity:  ,  
  8. The Liouville function:  

Exercises

edit
  • Exercise 2.1.1: Compute  ,   and  .
  • Exercise 2.1.2: Compute  . Hint:  .
  • Exercise 2.1.3: Compute   up to three decimal places. Hint: Use a Taylor expansion.
  • Exercise 2.1.4: Prove that for each   and    .

The convolution and the ring of arithmetic functions

edit

Definition 2.3:

Let   be arithmetical functions. Then the convolution of   and   is defined to be the function

 .

In the following theorem, we show that the arithmetical functions form an Abelian monoid, where the monoid operation is given by the convolution. Further, since the sum of two arithmetic functions is again an arithmetic function, the arithmetic functions form a commutative ring. In fact, as we shall also see, they form an integral domain.

Theorem 2.4 (Abelian monoid properties of the arithmetical functions):

  1. The convolution is commutative, i. e.  .
  2. The convolution is associative, i. e.  .
  3. The function   from definition 2.2 is an identity for the convolution, i. e.  .

Proof:

1.:

 ,

where   is a bijection from the set of divisors of   to itself.

2.:

 ,

where the last equality follows from the identity function

 

being a bijection. But

 

and hence associativity.

3.:

  

Theorem 2.5:

The ring of arithmetic functions is an integral domain.

Proof: Let   be arithmetic functions, and let   be minimal such that  ,  . Then

 . 

We shall now determine the units of the ring of arithmetic functions.

Theorem 2.6:

Let   be an arithmetic function. Then   is invertible (with respect to convolution) if and only if  .

Proof:

Assume first  . Then for any arithmetic function  ,  .

Assume now  . Then  , given by the recursive formula

 ,
 ,  

is an inverse (and thus the inverse) of  , since   and for   inductively

 

 

Exercises

edit
  • Exercise 2.2.1:
  • Exercise 2.2.2:

Multiplicative functions

edit

Definition 2.7:

An arithmetical function   is called multiplicative iff it satisfies

  1.  , and
  2.  .

Theorem 2.8:

Let   be multiplicative arithmetical functions. Then   is multiplicative.

Proof:

Let  . Then

 ,

since the function   is a bijection from the divisors of   to the Cartesian product of the divisors of   and the divisors of  ; this is because multiplication is the inverse:

 ,  .

To rigorously prove this actually is an exercise in itself. But due to the multiplicativity of   and  ,

 .

Furthermore,  . 

Since   is multiplicative, we conclude that the multiplicative functions form an Abelian submonoid of the arithmetic functions with convolution. Unfortunately, we do not have a subring since the sum of two multiplicative functions is never multiplicative (look at  ).

Theorem 2.9:

Let   be a multiplicative function such that   converges absolutely. Then

 .

Proof: Let   be the ordered sequence of all prime numbers. For all   we have

 

due to the multiplicativity of  . For each  , we successively take  , ...,   and then  . It follows from the definitions and the rule   that the right hand side converges to

 .

We claim that

 .

Indeed, choose   such that

 .

Then by the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, there exists an   and   such that

 .

Then we have by the triangle inequality for  ,   and   arbitrary that

 

From this easily follows the claim.

It is left to show that the product on the left is independent of the order of multiplication. But this is clear since if the sequence   is enumerated differently, the argument works in just the same way and the left hand side remains the same. 

Definition 2.10:

An arithmetical function   is called strongly multiplicative iff it satisfies

  1.  , and
  2.  .

Equivalently, a strongly multiplicative function is a monoid homomorphism  .

Theorem 2.11:

Let   be a strongly multiplicative function such that   converges absolutely. Then

 .

Proof:

Due to theorem 2.9, we have

 .

Due to strong multiplicativity and the geometric series, the latter expression equals

 . 

Exercises

edit
  • Exercise 2.3.1: Let   be an arithmetic function such that for all    , and let  . Prove that the function   is multiplicative.

Bell series

edit

Definition 2.12:

Let   be an arithmetic function. Then for a prime   the Bell series modulo   is the formal power series

 .

Examples 2.13:

We shall here compute the Bell series for some important arithmetic functions.

We note that in general for a completely multiplicative function  , we have

 .

In particular, in this case the Bell series defines a function.

1. The Kronecker delta:

 

2. Euler' totient function (we use lemma 9.?):

 

3. The Möbius   function:

 

4. The von Mangoldt function:

 

5. The monomials:

 

6. The number of distinct prime divisors:

 

7. The number of prime divisors including multiplicity:

 

8. The Liouville function:

 

Theorem 2.14 (compatibility of Bell series and convolution):

Let   arithmetic functions, and   be a prime. Then

 .

Proof:

  

In case of multiplicativity, we have the following theorem:

Theorem 2.15 (Uniqueness theorem):

Let   be multiplicative functions. Then

 .

Proof:   is pretty obvious;  :   as formal power series is equivalent to saying  . If now  , then

 

due to the multiplicativity of   and  . 

In chapter 9, we will use Bell series to obtain equations for number-theoretic functions.

Derivatives

edit

Definition 2.16:

Let   be an arithmetic function. Then the derivative of   is defined to be the function

 .

Theorem 2.17 (rules for the derivative):

Let   arithmetic functions. We have the following rules:

  1.  
  2.  
  3.   if   invertible, i.e. 

Note that   is not the inverse function of   (this wouldn't make much sense anyway since   arithmetic can not be surjective, since   is uncountable), but rather the convolution inverse.

Proof:

1. is easily checked.

2.:

 

3.

We have   and  . Hence, by 2.

 .

Convolving with   and using   yields the desired formula. 

Note that a chain rule wouldn't make much sense, since   arithmetic may map anywhere but to   and thus   doesn't make a lot of sense in general.

Further reading

edit